Human Lives with the Best Good
Aristotle's First and Second Best Human Lives
"In the other animals choice does not exist, nor in man at every age or
condition; for neither does deliberating and judgment about the why. It is
possible that many have an opinion whether a thing is to be done, but they do not have it
through reasoning"
(Eudemian Ethics II.10.1226b).
"Even some of the animals we say are sensible (φρόνιμα), namely those which
display a capacity for forethought as regards their own lives"
(Nicomachean Ethics VI.7.1141a).
So, for example, in the
History of Animals IX.5.611a,
Aristotle reports that deer give birth alongside the road where fear of humans
keeps predators from approaching. The deer, in this way, as Aristotle
understands them, are "sensible."
Aristotle thinks that animals have the capacity for
perception and that along with this capacity there is a capacity for desire.
Animals must behave in certain ways if they are
to survive. Perception is how they become aware of their circumstances, and
desire is what moves them to engage in appropriate behavior in these circumstances.
Human beings develop reason as they become adults. One of the parts of the reason they develop is the λογιστικόν.
It gives human beings the power to deliberate.
Animals and children lack the λογιστικόν. Deliberation is a kind of reasoning, and animals and children cannot engage in reasoning because they do not have reason.
Living by making Choices
"Wish is in the part with reason, and appetite and spirit is in the part
without reason"
(On the Soul III.9.432b).
"Now the origin of action--the from which of the movement, not the for sake of which--is
choice, and the origin of choice is desire together with reason that aims
at some goal"
(Nicomachean Ethics VI.2.1039a).
"Choice is not wish. We wish for ends,
but choose means; we wish to be healthy, for example, but choose
things to make us healthy"
(Nicomachean Ethics III.4.1111b).
"Choice is deliberate desire"
(Nicomachean Ethics III.5.1113a).
"It is
intellect qualified by desire or desire qualified by thought,
and what originates in this way is human"
(Nicomachean Ethics VI.2.1139b).
The λογιστικόν is the part with the power to think about what to do to bring about an
end.
This thinking involves the form of desire Aristotle calls "wish" (βούλησις). Wish is the desire that belongs to reason and that stems from beliefs about what is good and what is bad.
Deliberation is thinking about how to bring about a wished for end.
If deliberation shows that taking some action is the best way to bring about a wished for end, then there is a desire to take this action. Aristotle calls this desire "choice" (προαίρεσις).
Human beings also can act on the basis of a desire that belongs to one of the nonrational parts of the soul. They have this in common with animals and children.
Competency in Choosing
The virtue proper to the λογιστικόν is "practical wisdom" (φρόνησις).
Practical wisdom is competency in choosing.
Someone with this virtue of thought wishes for the correct ends (because he knows what is good and what is bad), deliberates correctly about how to bring about these ends, chooses in accord with his deliberation for the sake of these ends, has no desires contrary to his choices, and moves in accord with his choices unless something external impedes him.
"We cannot be
fully good without practical wisdom or practically wise
without virtue of character"
(Nicomachean Ethics VI.13.1144b).
Someone is not practically wise simply by knowing; he must also act on his
knowledge"
(Nicomachean Ethics VII.10.1152a).
"Socrates' inquiries were in one way correct and in another way in error.
... In the thought that all the virtues of character require practical wisdom,
he was right. ... Socrates, though, thought that the virtues are reason because he thought
they are knowledge, whereas we think they involve reason"
(Nicomachean Ethics VI.13.1144b).
Someone has practical wisdom if, and only if, he has the virtues of character.
In the case of courage, he "stands firm against the right things and fears the right things, for the right end, in the right way, at the right time" (Nicomachean Ethics III.7.1115b).
The Problem of Unreasonable Desires
Without the virtue of practical wisdom, there is a lack of competency in choosing.
One thing that could go wrong is that action is on impulse rather than reason.
ἀκρασία, noun, "want of power, incontinence"
ἀκρατής, adjective, "without command over oneself"
ἐγκρατής, adjective, "holding fast, master of oneself"
"The following are opinions held. Self-restraint and endurance are good and
praiseworthy. Unrestraint and softness are bad and blameworth. The self-restrained
abides by his calculation. The unrestrained
abandons it. The unrestrained knows that his actions are base, but he does them
because of passion. The self-restrained knows that his appetites are base, but
because of reason he does not follow them"
(Nicomachean Ethics VII.6.1145b)
Aristotle provides an example in what he calls "impetuous ἀκρασία."
"The impetuous are led by passion because they do not stop to deliberate" (Nicomachean Ethics VII.7.1150b) about what to do to live according to their beliefs about what is good and what is bad. When someone impetuous is insulted, he can get so upset and angry that his anger preempts any thought he might have had about how he should respond in the situation. Once he calms down, he might realize that in general he does not think that his angry response is appropriate. At the time, though, he did not think. He just acted out of his anger.
In this example, the "part [of the soul] with reason" is not in control of the "part with reason as its controller." This happens because of something that happend in the past. The impetuous failed to submit himself to the training necessary to ensure that "the part with reason as its controller" has reasonable desires, that he acts for reasons, rather than from passion, and hence that, if there is a conflict, he acts on the basis of "the part [of the soul] with reason."
The "continent" (ἐγκρατής) provides another example of the problem of unreasonable desires. Both the continent and the "incontinent" (ἀκρατής) have unreasonable desires. The continent, however, unlike the incontinent, does not act on these desires. The incontinent is weak. The continent is strong. Aristotle thinks that neither has practical wisdom.
The Happiest Human Life
Aristotle finds confirmation in common beliefs for his conclusion
that the contemplative life is the happiest.
"Happiness is not found in amusement; for it would be absurd if the end were
amusement, and our lifelong efforts and sufferings aimed at amusing ourselves.
For we choose practically everything for some other end--except for happiness, since is
the end; but serious work and toil aimed only at amusement appears stupid and excessively
childish.
Rather, it seems correct to amuse ourselves so that we can do something serious, as
Anacharsis says; for amusement would seem to be relaxation, and it is because we can not
toil continuously that we require relaxation. Relaxation, then, is not the end, since
we pursue it to prepare for activity"
(Nicomachean Ethics X.6.1176b).
Little is unknown about Anacharis. For some description, see
Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers I.8.
"Happiness seems to be found [most] in leisure (σχολῇ), since we accept trouble so that
we can be at leisure, and fight wars so that we can be at peace. The virtues
concerned with action have activities in politics or war, and these
require trouble. This seems completely true for actions in war,
since no one chooses to fight a war, and no one continues it, for the sake
of fighting. He would be a murderer if he made his friends
his enemies so that there were battles and killings"
(Nicomachean Ethics X.7.1177b).
"The activity of the intellect, it seems, is superior in excellence because
it is the activity of contemplation, aims at no end beyond itself, and his its own
pleasure proper, which augments its activity.
Further,
self-sufficiency, leisuredness, such freedom from fatigue as is possible for
man, and all other features assigned to the blessed, are features of this
activity"
(Nicomachean Ethics X.7.1177b).
"It seems likely that the man who whose activity is according to the intellect, and who cultivates his intellect and keeps it in the
best condition, is also the man most beloved of the gods. For if they
pay attention to us, as they seem to,
it would be reasonable for them to take pleasure in that part of man
which is best and most akin to themselves, namely the intellect"
(Nicomachean Ethics X.8.1179a).
Now that we have a better understanding of the virtues of wisdom and practical wisdom,
we can see better how Aristotle understands the human lives with "the best good."
They are the lives with practical wisdom and the lives with practical wisdom and wisdom.
Someone who lives the first of these lives, even if he has the external goods necessary for happiness, does not achieve the full human potential. The ἐπιστημονικόν does not have its proper virtue. This life does not include the activity of contemplation.
Given the external goods, Aristotle thinks the second of these lives is the more complete performance of the human function and hence is the happier of the two lives.
Aristotle's argument for this conclusion depends on a premise Socrates uses in the Republic.
"What is proper to the nature of each thing is best and most pleasant for it. For a human being, this is the life in accord with the [virtue of the] intellect if the intellect, more than anything else, is man. And this life, then, will also be the happiest" (Nicomachean Ethics X.7.1178a).
Aristotle, Plato, and Socrates
Aristotle intends for this conclusion about the "best good" to have practical consequences. In this, he stands squarely in the Socratic tradition of trying to benefit those who engage with him. Aristotle realizes that practical wisdom is not something many of us will achieve and that even fewer of us will become wise, but he thinks that if we have this target in mind, we are more likely to increase the level of happiness we experience in our lives.
Aristotle is part of this Socratic tradition, but he also follows Plato against Socrates.
Whereas Socrates thought the kind of knowledge the inquirers into nature sought might not be possible and that it is not the wisdom that interests him even if it is possible, Plato moves away from this perspective. In the Phaedo and the Republic and then more so in the Timaeus, a life is good and the person living it is happy to the extent that he knows the most general and theoretical aspects of how the universe is. Aristotle tempers this thought in Plato. He makes room for Socrates' life as a life of practical wisdom in which this knowledge and thus contemplation is absent, but he does not think it is the best life for a human being to live.
Aristotle, in this way, is a man of his times. He tries to correct the views of Plato he thinks are mistaken, and he tries to give better arguments for the ones he thinks are true.
Perseus Digital Library
Aristotle,
Nicomachean Ethics,
Eudemian Ethics
Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon
αἵρεσις, hairesis, noun, "choice"
ἀκούσιος (Attic contraction for ἀεκούσιος), akousios, adjective, "unwilling"
ἑκούσιος, hekousios, adjective, "willing"
ἀκρασία,
akrasia, noun, alternate spelling of
ἀκράτεια,
akrateia, "want of power, incontinence."
"It would be astonishing, Socrates thought, for knowledge to be in someone, but
be mastered (κρατεῖν) by something else, and dragged around like a slave. Socrates fought
against the account, in the belief there is no incontinence (ἀκρασίας)"
(Nicomachean Ethics VII.2).
βουλεύω, bouleuō, verb, "take counsel, deliberate"
βούλησις, boulēsis, noun, "willing"
προαίρεσις, proairesis, noun, "choice"
διανοητικός, dianoētikos, adjective, "intellectual"
νόος, noos, noun, "mind"
φρήν, phrēn, noun, "the wit of a person"
φρόνησις, phronēsis, noun, "practical wisdom"
φρόνιμος, phronimos, adjective, "in one's right mind, in one's senses, showing the presence of mind, sensible"
"In Aristotle's view, there is a certain good which we all will or want to
attain in life, namely, a good life. As grown-up human beings we have a certain
conception, though different people have rather different ones, of what this
final good consists of. So in a particular situation we shall, as mature human
beings, choose what to do in light of our conception of this final good, because
we think, having deliberated about the matter, that acting in this way will help
us attain this good"
(Michael Frede, A Free Will
Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought, 27).
"As then the question of legislation has been left uninvestigated by previous
thinkers, it will perhaps be well if we consider it for ourselves, together
with the whole question of the constitution of the city, in order to complete
as far as possible our philosophy of human
affairs (τὰ ἀνθρώπεια φιλοσοφία)"
(Nicomachean Ethics X.9.1181b).
"Now it is clear that the best constitution is the system under which anybody whatsoever would be best off and
would live in felicity; but the question is raised even on the part of those who agree that the life
accompanied by virtue is the most desirable, whether the life of citizenship and practical things is desirable or
rather a life released from all external affairs, for example some form of contemplative life, which is
said by some to be the only life that is philosophic" (Politics VII.2.1324a).
"Aristotle hardly
ever talks of ethics or practical philosophy as 'philosophy.'' One place in
which he does so is at the very end of E.N [Ethica
Nicomachea or (translated from the Latin into English) Nicomachean
Ethics].X.9.1181b15, where he speaks of 'the philosophy concerning human
affairs.' Thus he implicitly contrasts it with first
philosophy which is concerned with wisdom which is divine
and of matters divine, for instance God. It is wisdom which affords us the
contemplation of truth, of which Aristotle earlier in E.N.X
tells us that it makes our life like that of gods, to the extent that this is
humanly possible. But first philosophy is concerned with the good or with what
is best, and its concern is a theoretical concern, a concern aimed at
satisfying our need to know and understand what is the most important thing to
understand, namely, God, a principle of all things. By contrast, ethics is
just concerned with the human good, and this concern is not theoretical, but a
practical concern. It is aimed at being good and living well"
(Michael Frede, "Aristotle's Account of the Origins of Philosophy," 24.
Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, 2004, 9-44).