The First Unmovable Mover
Aristotle's Theory of the "For Something" in Nature
Aristotle thinks that specific behavior (the behavior common to the species) has a teleological explanation. It happens "for something and because it is better" (Physics II.8.198b).
In the case of reason, Aristotle thinks that human beings naturally acquire this ability in the process of induction as they change from children to adults. Induction changes human beings as they mature so that they become like the first unmovable mover. Aristotle thinks that its existence is good and that other things naturally change to become like it.
Aristotle develops his teleology against the background of the explanations in the Timaeus. He follows Plato in thinking that the explanation of order must be in terms of a mind. This drives them to an understanding of the world that can seem strange and implausible to us.
Teleological Causation in Plato's Universe
"There is something which must be considered first about the entire heaven or cosmos or if there is any other name which it specially prefers, by that let us call it. We must first investigate concerning it this fundamental question that must be considered at the outset in relation to anything: whether it always was with no beginning in generation or has come to be having originated from some beginning. The cosmos has come to be, for it is both visible, tangible and it has a body, and all such things are perceptible, and all perceptible things are grasped by opinion and the senses and, as we said [Timaeus 27d], come into being and are generated. What’s more, we say that a thing which has come to be has, of necessity, come to be through some cause. Now to discover the maker and father of this universe is a task indeed, and having discovered him it is impossible to describe him to everyone" (Timaeus 28b). In the Timaeus, as we have seen, there is an explanation for why things are the way they are.
"Let us state the reason why becoming and the universe were constructed by the artificer. He was good, and in the good no envy ever arises about anything and, being devoid of envy he desired that all things be as much like himself as possible" (Timaeus 29d).
"Let us conclude our discussion of the auxiliary causes that gave our eyes the
power they now possess. We must next speak of that supremely beneficial
function for which the god gave them to us. As my account has it, our sight
has proved to be a source of supreme benefit to us, in that none of our
present statements about the universe could ever have been made if we had
never seen any stars, sun or heaven. The ability to see the periods of
day-and-night, of months and of years, of equinoxes and solstices, has led to
the invention of number, and has given us the idea of time and opened the path
to inquiry into the nature of the universe. These pursuits have given us the
love of wisdom, a gift from the god to the mortal race whose value neither has
been nor ever will be surpassed. This is the supreme good our eyesight offers
us. ... The god invented sight and gave it to us so that we might observe the
orbits of intelligence in the universe and apply them to the revolutions of
our own understanding. For there is a kinship between them, even though our
revolutions are disturbed, whereas the universal orbits are undisturbed. So
once we have come to know them and to share their ability to make correct
calculations according to nature, we should stabilize the straying revolutions
within ourselves by imitating the completely unstraying revolutions of the
god"
(Timaeus 46e).
One way the divine maker ensures that human beings are like him and thus are
good is by ensuring that they have the sense of sight. Through this
sense human beings make themselves better by making their minds more
orderly. Timaeus thinks that seeing is part of a process that gives rise to
the love of wisdom and that ultimately transforms human beings so that their
thinking "imitat[es] the completely unstraying revolutions of the god." This god is the
universe. The universe is alive. The divine maker makes it as a soul within a body.
Teleology without the Divine Maker
Timaeus's teleological explanation is the immediate antecedent for Aristotle's idea that human beings acquire reason for the sake of becoming like the first unmovable mover.
Aristotle removes the divine maker, but not the teleology, from Timaeus's explanation.
In the Metaphysics XII, Aristotle argues that there can be no first or last moment of time, that time is an attribute of change, and that the ultimate cause of the changes that occur in the universe (such as the development of reason in induction) must be free from the possibility of change. Otherwise, Aristotle argues, "if its substance is potentiality, there will not be eternal motion, since that which exists potentially may not exist" (Metaphysics XII.1071b).
This conception of time and change rules out a teleological explanation of things in terms of divine maker understood on the model of an artificer as Plato presents it in the Timaeus, but Aristotle does not reject teleological explanation itself. In the place of the divine maker, Aristotle thinks that "the first mover, which is immovable" (τὸ πρῶτον κινοῦν ἀκίνητον) is the starting-point for the teleological explanation of change in the universe.
Teleological Causation in Aristotle's Universe
The Fixed Stars:
Most of the visible objects in the night sky appear to move together in the same
relative arrangement night after night. These objects are the fixed stars. They
appear to lie on a spherical surface surrounding the earth and to rotate about
the north-south axis once per sidereal day.
A sidereal day is (a day relative to the stars) is the time it takes for the
earth to rotate once on its axis so that the fixed stars appear to return again
their prior locations. A solar day is about four minutes shorter.
Stars rising seen looking to the East
The Wandering Stars:
Relative to the fixed stars, some of the visible objects (the planets)
appear to move differently. They are the "wandering stars"
(ἀστέρες πλανῆται). In terms of spheres, their apparent motion is more
difficult to explain. One way to model the motion is terms of nested spheres.
Retrograde motion of Mars
"In order that time
might come into being, Sun, moon and the five other stars (ἄστρα) which are called wanderers (πλανητά) were
generated [by the god] to define and protect the numbers of time"
(Timaeus 38c).
"All the unwandering stars have
come into being, divine everlasting creatures which abide forever, revolving in the same way in
the same place. But those that turn back and keep wandering in this fashion have come into being
in the manner we described before"
(Timaeus 40b).
In the universe, as Aristotle understands it, there is
an outermost sphere
with earth at its center. This is the sphere of the fixed (as opposed to wandering) stars
in the heavens.
Aristotle explains the motion of the fixed stars teleologically.
These fixed stars (to us on earth appear to) move with a continuous circular motion, and Aristotle thought the first unmovable mover is the teleological cause of this motion. It causes this motion without itself changing in any way. Aristotle thought that eternally moving in a circle is a behavior in which the fixed stars engage because this is how they make their existence like the perfect existence the first unmovable mover enjoys.
Argument for the First Unmovable Mover
Aristotle's argument for the first unmovable mover proceeds as follows.
Because motion is an attribute of time and there is no first or last moment of time, there must be eternal and continuous motion. This motion is the circular motion of the fixed stars and what we see when we look to the heavens. This motion must have a cause, and because the motion is eternal and cannot change, the cause must be "eternal and immutable."
"There must be some substance which is eternal and immutable. Substances are the primary reality, and if they are all perishable, everything is perishable. But motion cannot be either generated or destroyed, for it always existed; nor can time, because there can be no priority or posteriority if there is no time. Hence as time is continuous, so too is motion; for time is either identical with motion or an affection of it. But there is no continuous motion except that which is spatial, of spatial motion only that which is circular" (Metaphysics XII.7.1071b).
"There is something eternally moved with an unceasing motion, and this unceasing motion is circular motion. This is evident not only argument but also in fact [since we see this motion]. The first heaven [of the fixed stars], then, must be eternal, and something must move it. Since that which is moved and moves is intermediate, there must be a mover which moves without being moved, it itself being eternal, substance, actuality" (Metaphysics XII.7.1072a).
"[This actuality is the] "first mover, which [itself] is immovable" (Metaphysics XII.7.1074a).
The Realm Below the Sphere of the Heavens
In the realm below the heavens, sensible substances do not exist eternally and so have ways of becoming like the first unmovable mover other than eternally moving in a circle.
Acquiring reason in induction is an example. It is caused teleologically. Acquiring reason in induction is a way human existence naturally becomes like the existence of the first unmovable mover. Acquiring reason and its knowledge is a step in the direction of the θεωρία or "contemplation" that characterizes the life and existence of the first unmovable mover.
"[The first unmovable mover] is the starting-point upon which the heaven and nature depend. Its life is like the best which we temporarily enjoy. It must be in that state always, which for us is impossible.... Actuality is thought to be the intellect the divine possesses, and contemplation is that which is most pleasant and best. ... If, then, the state the god always enjoys is as great as that which we enjoy sometimes, it is marvelous; and if it is greater, this is still more marvelous. Nevertheless it is so. Moreover, life belongs to god. For the actuality of intellect is life, and god is that actuality; and the essential actuality of god is life most good and eternal. We hold, then, that god is a living being, eternal, most good" (Metaphysics XII.7.1072b).
The Forms of Sensible Substances
The form of a sensible substance is thus not just an organization of material.
It is an organization for the sake of the existence of something that (as much as the material allows) has an existence like the perfect existence of the first unmovable mover.
One such organization is the form of a human being. Human beings, because of the forms that are their natures, develop reason as they become adults. This is good for them, and it is not a coincidence that they develop reason as they mature and that the development of reason is good for them. It is part of knowing what a form in matter is, according to Aristotle, that the first unmovable mover exists and is the teleological cause of regularities in nature.
"First, then, we must speak of food and reproduction; for the nutritive soul belongs to all other living creatures besides man, and is the first and most widely shared faculty of the soul, in virtue of which they all have life. Its functions are reproduction and the assimilation of food, as a living thing that has reached its normal development and is unmutilated, and whose mode of generation is not spontaneous, naturally produces another like itself, an animal producing an animal, and a plant a plant, in order that, as far as its nature allows, it may partake in the eternal and divine (τοῦ ἀεὶ καὶ τοῦ θείου). Each strives for this and for the sake of this performs all its natural functions. ... However, since they cannot share in the eternal and divine by continuity of existence, because no perishable thing can remain numerically one and the same, they share in these in the only way they can, some to a greater and some to a lesser extent; what persists is not the individual itself, but something in its image, not one in number but one in form" (On the Soul II.4.415a). This is true for the nonhuman animals and plants too. They "partake in the divine" by reproducing and thus by making another like themselves. It is not a coincidence that they have this behavior and that it is good for them. The behavior is their way of being like the unchanging existence of the first unmovable mover. Aristotle says that "since they cannot share in the eternal and divine by continuity of existence, because no perishable thing can remain numerically one and the same, they share in these in the only way they can."
Our Thinking has Changed
It does appear that members of species have their specific behavior because it benefits them, but the details of Aristotle's explanation for this are no longer at all plausible to us.
Plato and Aristotle saw gods when they looked up to the sky.
Against the charge that he does not believe in the traditional gods, Socrates replies that he with the rest of mankind believes that "the sun and the moon are gods" (Apology 26d).
This outlook now seems strange to us because we no longer are so ready to insist that the explanation of order and regularity must be in terms of something intelligent.
Perseus Digital Library
Plato,
Timaeus.
Aristotle,
Metaphysics.
Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon
κόσμος, kosmos, noun, "order"
"Aristotle thinks that we can argue from the fact that there always has been
motion and always will be motion and that there is no beginning or end to
time, that there must be at least one continuous eternal and hence cyclical
motion. Hence there must be at least one eternal body which eternally moves
continuously in a cycle. To account for this motion we have to assume a mover
which eternally moves the body. But such a mover must itself be immaterial,
not subject to any change or motion. So we have at least two items, an eternal
body in eternal periodic motion, and an immaterial unmoved mover. These two
items are minimally necessary, Aristotle argues, for there always to be change
and for there always to be time"
(Michael Frede, "Introduction," 30-31. Aristotle's Metaphysics Lambda, 1-52).
"Arguably Aristotle takes his primary philosophy to be the counterpart of
Plato's dialectic. As is clear from Met. Z[VII].16 1040b27-1041a13,
Aristotle thinks that in a way Plato was right in postulating immaterial separate
forms, except that he was wrong in the way he identified them, namely as
Platonic ideas, rather than as eternal substances, namely immaterial intellects
of the kind Aristotle discusses in Met. Λ[XII]. The place of the idea
of the good [in Plato] will be taken by the first unmoved mover. Moreover, Aristotle in
arguing that, and trying to show how, primary philosophy is universal, somehow
deals with whatever there is quite generally, though it has a specific domain,
namely unchanging separate substances, is just mirroring the Platonic
assumption that dialectic, though concerned specifically with the forms, provides
universal knowledge, given that the forms are the principals of everything"
(Michael Frede, "Aristotle's Account of the Origins of Philosophy," 42.
Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, 2004, 9-44).