ARISTOTLE
Selected Passages from the Aristotelian Corpus
**** This page is under construction ****
Deduction, Demonstration, and Knowledge
In the Prior and Posterior Analytics, Aristotle discusses deduction and demonstration respectively. These texts belong to the logical works, which are first in the Aristotelian corpus.
•
Prior Analytics I.1.24b
συλλογισμός, syllogismos, "computation, calculation."
A deduction (συλλογισμός) is an argument in which, certain things having been
supposed, something different from those supposed results of necessity because
of their being so.
Notes on the Text
The translation of συλλογισμός as "deduction" can be misleading. We think that some deductions are valid and others are not. In this language, a συλλογισμός is a valid deduction.
•
Prior Analytics I.4.25b
The reason why we must deal with deduction before we deal with
demonstration is that deduction is more universal; for demonstration
(ἀπόδειξις) is a kind of deduction, but not every deduction is a
demonstration.
Notes on the Text
Every demonstration is a deduction, but not every deduction is a demonstration. To be a demonstration, a deduction must have several further properties.
•
Posterior Analytics I.71b
"Since what is known without qualification cannot be otherwise, what is
known by demonstrative knowledge will be necessary. Now knowledge is
demonstrative when we possess it in virtue of having a demonstration;
therefore the premises from which demonstration is inferred are
necessarily true"
(Posterior Analytics I.73a).
"Knowledge is a taking up (ὑπόληψις) about universals (καθόλου), things that are
by necessity"
(Nicomachean Ethics VI.6.1140b).
"[W]isdom is the most exact [form of] knowledge. The wise man
must not only know what follows from the starting-points, but also must have
the truth of the start-points. Hence, wisdom is intellect and knowledge
(ἡ σοφία νοῦς καὶ ἐπιστήμη).... [It] is knowledge and intellect about what
is most honorable by nature"
(Nicomachean Ethics VI.7.1141b).
We think we know a thing without qualification, and not in the sophistic,
accidental way, whenever we think we know the cause (αἰτίαν) in virtue of
which something is—that it is the cause of that very thing—and also know
that this cannot be otherwise. Clearly, knowledge is something of this
sort.
Notes on the Text
Aristotle restricts "knowledge" (ἐπιστήμη) to necessary truths. It grasps consequence and incompatibility among universals, both immediate and deductive.
So although 'knowledge' is the traditional translation of ἐπιστήμη, Aristotle's conception of "knowledge" is not the one reflected in the meaning of the English word.
Aristotle takes himself to describing "knowledge without qualification." This can be puzzling. To us, it can seem that something is knowledge or it is not.
What, then, is going on?
•
Posterior Analytics I.71b
Whether there is any other method of knowing will be discussed later. Our
contention now is that we do at any rate obtain knowledge by demonstration. By
demonstration I mean a deduction that produces knowledge, in other words one
which enables us to know by the mere fact that we grasp it.
Now if knowledge is such as we have assumed, knowledge must proceed from
premises which are true, primary, immediate, better known than, prior to, and
causative of the conclusion. On these conditions only will the first
principles be properly applicable to the fact which is to be proved. Syllogism
indeed will be possible without these conditions, but not demonstration; for
the result will not be knowledge.
Notes on the Text
For a deduction to be a demonstration, "true, primary, immediate..." are necessary.
•
Posterior Analytics I.72b
Not all knowledge is demonstrative. The knowledge of immediate premises
is not by demonstration. It is evident that this must be so; for if it
is necessary to know the prior premises from which the demonstration
proceeds, and if the regress ends with the immediate premises, the
latter must be indemonstrable. Such is our contention on this point.
Indeed we hold not only that knowledge is possible, but that there is a
definite starting point (ἀρχὴν) of knowledge by which we recognize
definitions (ᾗ τοὺς ὅρους γνωρίζομεν).
Notes on the Text
Someone who grasps a demonstration has knowledge. He knows that the conclusion of the demonstration is true. His knowledge of the conclusion is "demonstrative."
Not all knowledge is demonstrative. Someone who grasps a demonstration has demonstrative knowledge of its conclusion. He also knows that the premises of the demonstration are true, but this knowledge need not be demonstrative. If these premises are themselves the conclusions of demonstrations, then the knowledge is demonstrative. This regress, however, must stop with knowledge that is not demonstrative. Hence not all knowledge is demonstrative.
The philosophical problem is to understand this nondemonstrative knowledge.
Aristotle provides his answer with his theory of induction.