The Tripartite Theory of the Soul
Desire in the Three Parts of the Soul
The parts of the soul are "powers" or "faculties."
The Latin
facultas is a translation of the
Greek
δύναμις.
Aristotle has
a version of the tripartite theory. The Platonists and Aristotelians in later anquity
also have a version.
In Socratic Intellectualism and the Tripartite theory,
rational does not have the same meaning as reasonable.
The thinking in reason
can be reasonable or unreasonable, but it is rational by definition.
It is thinking that belongs to reason.
In the Republic, Plato has Socrates argue that the soul is tripartite. This theory
of the soul, like the one Socrates expresses in the Protagoras,
is a theory of the human mind.
The Three Parts of the Soul
On the Tripartite theory, reason is not the only power of the mind. In addition to this rational part, the soul has nonrational parts. These parts are traditionally called spirit and appetite.
- reason, τὸ λογιστικὸν
- spirit, τὸ θυμοειδές
- appetite, τὸ ἐπιθυμητικόν
To understand the Triparite Theory as a way of thinking about human beings, it is necessary to understand what is true of a human being because his soul has these three parts.
Rational and Nonrational Desire
A human being with these parts of the soul has desires. The desires of reason are his rational desires. The desires of appetite and spirit are his nonrational desires.
This is not the understanding of desire we saw in Socratic Intellectualism. According to this theory of the soul, there are no nonrational desires. This does not mean that all desires are reasonable. It means that all desires are beliefs about what is good and what is bad.
This is not true in the Tripartite Theory. On this theory, although the rational desires are beliefs about what is good and what is bad, the nonrational desires are not. The nonrational desires are beliefs, but the beliefs are not about what is good and what is bad.
The conception of desire, then, on the Tripartite Theory of the Soul, is less "intellectual." Desires are still beliefs, as they are in Socratic Intellectualism, but not all the beliefs are the ones about what is good and what is bad we form in an exercise of reason.
The Parts of the Soul can Conflict
"If the pleasant is good, no one who has knowledge or thought of other actions as
better and as possible for him to do, will do as he proposes if he is free to do
the better ones; and this yielding to oneself is nothing but ignorance, and
mastery of oneself is wisdom"
(Protagoras 358b).
"this yielding to oneself is nothing but ignorance"
Someone might say that although he does y, he knows x is better. The facts, though,
according to Socrates, are different. His state of mind is ignorance, not knowledge.
An example helps show what Socrates means.
From my experiences of eating sweets,
I develop the belief that eating them is good. Later I become aware of the arguments
from medicine that this behavior is not healthy. I believe that my health is good. So
I resolve to stop eating sweets, but this itself does not cause me to stop believing
that eating them is good. When I act on this belief, it can be tempting to explain what
happened by saying that I know that eating sweets is bad but do it anyway because I
am overcome by pleasure. Socrates rejects this explanation. he thinks that I do not know
that eating sweets is bad as long as I continue to believe that eating them is good.
"The body fills us with passions and desires and fears, and all sorts of
fancies and foolishness"
(Phaedo 66c).
This difference has consequences for whether pleasure can overcome knowledge.
Socrates, in the Protagoras, as we have seen, argues that pleasure cannot overcome knowledge. In the experience we describe as being overcome by pleasure, what really happens is that we act on a belief we have trouble abandoning because we are not "masters of ourselves."
In the Republic, Socrates understands what happens in the experience of being overcome by pleasure as a failure of reason to rule. Reason is the "naturally better part" and should rule, but the two nonrational parts can have desires that conflict with the desires in reason.
"Yet is not the expression mastery of oneself ridiculous? He who
is stronger than himself would also presumably be weaker than himself, and he who is
weaker than himself, stronger, since the same person is induced by all these expressions.
Of course, Socrates.
Nonetheless, the expression seems to
me to mean that, in the soul there is a better part and a worse part and
that, whenever the naturally better part is in control of the worse, this is
expressed with the words mastery of oneself. This, at any rate, is a term of praise. But when the smaller and better part is
overpowered by the larger part, because of bad upbringing and certain company,
this is called yielding to one's self"
(Republic IV.430e).
On the theory Socrates has in mind here, it is possible to know that something is best but do something else because a desire in the "worse part" of the soul overpowers the desire in reason.
An Argument from Opposites
"It is obvious the same thing will never do or suffer
opposites in the same respect in relation to the same thing and at the same
time. So if ever we find this happening we shall know that it was not the
same thing but a plurality"
(Republic IV.436b).
"Now, wouldn’t you consider assent and dissent, wanting to
have something and rejecting it, taking something and pushing it way, as all
being pairs of mutual opposites—whether of opposite doings or of opposite
undergoings does not matter?
Yes, they are opposites.
What about thirst, hunger, and the appetites as a whole, and
also willing and wishing? Would you include all of them somewhere among
the kinds of things we just mentioned? For example, wouldn’t you say that
the soul of someone who has an appetite wants the thing for which it has
an appetite, and draws toward itself what it wishes to have; and, in addition,
that insofar as his soul wills something to be given to it, it nods assent to
itself as if in answer to a question, and strives toward its attainment?
I would
(Republic IV.437b).
"Thirst itself is in its nature only for drink itself.
Absolutely.
So the soul of the thirsty person, insofar as he is thirsty, does not
wish anything else but to drink, and it wants this and is impelled toward it.
Clearly"
(Republic IV.439b).
"Are we to say that some men sometimes though thirsty refuse to drink?
We are indeed, many and often.
What then, should one affirm about them? Is it not that there is something in
the soul that bids them to drink and a something that forbids, a different
something that masters (κρατοῦν) that which bids?
I think so.
And is it not the fact that that which inhibits such actions arises when it
arises from the calculations of reason (λογισμοῦ), but the impulses which draw
and drag come through affections and diseases?
Apparently.
Not unreasonably, shall we claim that they are two and different from one
another, naming that in the soul whereby it reckons and reasons the reasoning
part (λογιστικὸν) and that with which it loves, hungers, thirsts, and gets
passionately excited by other desires, the unreasoning (ἀλόγιστόν) and
appetitive part (ἐπιθυμητικόν)—companion of various repletions and
pleasures.
It would not be unreasonable but quite natural, Socrates"
(Republic IV.439c).
Cf. Phaedo 94b.
"Of the spirit (θυμοῦ), that with which we feel anger (θυμούμεθα), is it a
third, or would it be the same as these [we have distinguished]?
Perhaps with one of these, the appetitive.
But I once heard a story which I believe, that Leontius the son of Aglaion, on
his way up from the Peiraeus under the outer side of the northern wall, becoming
aware of dead bodies that lay at the place of public execution
knew a desire to see them
and at the same time was disgusted and turned away. For a time he
struggled and veiled his head, but finally, overpowered (κρατούμενος)
by his
desire,
he pushed his eyes wide open, rushed up to the corpses, and
cried, 'There, you
wretches, take your fill of the fine spectacle!'
I too have heard the story.
Yet, surely, this anecdote signifies that anger sometimes
fights against desires, as one thing against another.
Yes, it does, Socrates"
(Republic IV.439e).
"And don’t we often notice on other occasions that when
desires force (βιάζωνταί) someone contrary to his rational calculation, he reproaches
himself and feels anger at the thing in him that is doing the forcing; and just
as if there were two warring factions, such a person’s spirit becomes the ally
of his reason? But spirit partnering with appetite to do what reason has
decided should not be done—I do not imagine you would say that you had
ever seen that, in yourself or in anyone else.
No, by Zeus, I would not"
(Republic IV.440a).
"So in the soul, there is the spirited part (θυμοειδές), which is the helper of
reason by nature unless it is corrupted by bad nurture?
We have to assume it as a third, Socrates.
Yes, provided it shall have been shown to be something different from the rational,
as it has been shown to be other than the appetitive.
That is not hard to be shown, Socrates. For that much one can see in children,
that they are from their birth full of rage and high spirit, but as
for reason, some of them, to my thinking, never participate in it, and the
majority quite late.
Yes, by heaven, excellently said, and further, one could see in animals
that what you say is true"
(Republic IV.441a).
"The same magnitude, I presume, viewed from near and from far does not
appear equal.
Why, no.
And the same things appear bent and straight to those who view them in water
and out, or concave and convex, owing to similar errors of vision about colors,
and there is obviously every confusion of this sort in our souls. And so
scene-painting in its exploitation of this weakness of our nature falls nothing
short of witchcraft, and so do jugglery and many other such contrivances.
True.
And have not measuring and numbering and weighing proved to be most gracious aids to
prevent the domination in our soul of the apparently greater or less or more or heavier,
and to give the control to that which has reckoned and numbered or even weighed?
Certainly.
But this surely would be the function of the part of the soul that reasons and
calculates (λογιστικοῦ).
Why, yes, of that.
And sometimes, when this has measured and declares that certain things are larger or
that some are smaller than the others or equal,
the opposite appears (φαίνεται) at the same time.
Yes.
And did we not say it is
impossible for the same thing at one time to believe (δοξάζειν) opposites about the same thing?
And we were right in affirming that.
The part of the soul, then,
that opines (δοξάζον) in contradiction of measurement could not be the same with that which
conforms to it.
Why, no.
Further, that which puts its trust in measurement and
reckoning must be the best part of the soul.
Surely.
That which opposes it
must belong to the inferior parts of the soul.
Necessarily.
This, then, was what I meant when I said that poetry, and
in general the mimetic art, produces a product that is far removed from truth in
the accomplishment of its task, and associates with the part in us that is
remote from intelligence (φρονήσεως), and is its companion and friend for no
sound and true purpose"
(Republic X.602c).
The Müller-Lyer Illusion.
The second horizontal line appears longer than than the first, but in fact the
two lines are the same in length.
An example Socrates gives helps us begin to understand what happens in this overpowering.
In the example, someone is thirsty but refuses to drink. In situations of this sort, Socrates thinks that there are opposite desires: one is in appetite and the other is in reason.
The desires are the desire to drink and the desire not to drink. Socrates thinks that because these desires move us in opposite ways, they must belong to different parts of the soul. He thinks that the soul moves the body and can simultaneously move it in opposite ways only if one part is moving it in one way and another part is moving it in the other way.
In addition to appetite and reason, Socrates believes that the soul also has a third part.
Socrates appeals to a story about Leontius to show that anger sometimes conflicts with the appetitive part of the soul. If this anger is not a matter of reason, it must belong to a third part of the soul. To show that anger like Leontius experienced is not a matter of reason, Glaucon supplies the argument. He says that "some [children]... never participate in [reason], and the majority quite late." So, since children get angry about their appetitive desires, and reason does not play a controlling role in their behavior, spirit is the third part in the soul.
The desires in the three parts of the soul are for different things.
Appetite has desires by having beliefs about food and other things that do and do not bring bodily pleasure. Spirit similarly has desires by having beliefs about what brings honor and what brings shame, and reason has desires by having beliefs about what is good and benefits us.
Another Argument for Reason
Socrates later gives another example to show that reason is one of the parts of the soul.
He says that sometimes when reason "has measured and declares that certain things are larger or that some are smaller than the others or equal, the opposite appears at the same time."
To begin to see what Socrates has in mind, suppose that lines are arranged in an Müller-Lyer Illusion so that one appears to us longer than the other. In this situation, even after measurement reveals to us that the lines are equal in length, the appearance that they are unequal persists because the arrangement of the lines tricks our eyes.
In this situation, he thinks the soul assents and dissents. There is the belief formed by assenting that the lines are the same thing, and there is the belief formed by dissenting that the lines not the same lenght. Socrates thinks that these beliefs must be in different parts of the soul.
In this, Socrates attributes "beliefs" (δόξαι) to the nonrational parts of the soul and talks about the part that "opines in contradiction of measurement" (Republic X.603a).
The example suggests that beliefs in the nonrational parts are representations produced by the senses, memory, and imagination, not by measurement, questioning, and other such methods.
Reason Should Rule the Soul
Different organizations of the parts of the soul are possible. Socrates thinks that in the proper organization, reason knows and rules, spirit is reason's ally, and appetite is under control.
"Does it not belong to the reasoning part to rule,
since it is wise and exercises foresight on behalf of
the whole soul, and for the spirited part to obey and be its
ally?
Assuredly, Socrates"
(Republic IV.441e).
It is not straightfoward to understand this and the other possible organizations.
In Socrates' example, "some men sometimes though thirsty refuse to drink." The men in this example do not drink, but the appetite in their souls "bids" them to drink.
Why does this "bidding" not result in drinking?
We cannot just say that the "bidding" does not result in drinking because reason "forbids" it. This does not explain why the "forbidding" wins out over the "bidding."
We are left, then, to think that the winning desire is the desire from the part of the soul that rules. When reason rules, the "forbidding" in reason wins over the "bidding" in appetite. When appetite rules, the "bidding" wins in appetite wins over the "forbidding" in reason.
Now we need to know how a part comes to be in control and to rule in the soul.
Training Appetite and Spirit
"[I]n children the first childish sensations are pleasure and pain,
and that it is in these first that virtue and vice come to the soul;
but as to wisdom and settled true opinions, a man is lucky if they come to him
even in old age and; he that is possessed of these blessings, and all that
they comprise, is indeed a perfect man. I term education, then, that in
which virtue first
comes to
children. When pleasure and love, and pain and hatred, spring up rightly in the souls
of those who are unable as yet to grasp the reason; and when, after grasping
reason, they consent thereunto that they have been rightly trained in
fitting practices:—this consent, viewed as a whole, is virtue, while the part of it
that is rightly trained in respect of pleasures and pains, so as to hate what ought to be
hated, right from the beginning up to the very end, and to love what ought to be
loved, if you were to mark this part off in your account and call it education,
you would be giving it, in my opinion, its right name"
(Laws II.653a).
Cf. Laws II.659d;
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics II.3.1104b.
Socrates explains that reason becomes the ruler in a process of education.
One of the aims of this education is train the appetitive and spirited parts so that they exist in harmony with reason and its beliefs about what is good and what is bad.
Because the young are "especially malleable and best take on whatever pattern one wishes to impress on" them, Socrates thinks that they are not "to hear any old stories made up by just anyone, then, and [in this way] to take beliefs into their souls that are, for the most part, the opposite of the ones we think they should hold when they are grown up" (Republic II.377b). Further, because first impressions in children are hard to change, he thinks that "the first stories they hear about virtue should be the right ones for them to hear" (Republic II.378e).
Stories about virtue mould the spirited part of the soul to like and dislike the appropriate things. Together with training for the appetite, this ensures that reason is the ruler.
"Since [the correctly educated] feels distaste correctly, he will praise fine things, be pleased by them, take them into his soul, and, through being nourished by them, become fine and good. The ugly or shameful, he will condemn and hate while he is still young, before he can grasp the reason. Because he has been so trained, he will welcome the reason when it comes and recognize it easily because of its kinship with himself" (Republic III.401e).
Knowledge is Not Enough
According to the Triparite Theory, then, although reason can rule, Socrates was wrong about how powerful knowledge is. He thought knowledge could not be "dragged around."
"What, Protagoras, do you believe about
knowledge? Do you go along with the many? They think this way
about it, that it is not powerful, neither a leader nor a ruler,
that while knowledge is often present, what rules is something else, sometimes
desire, sometimes pleasure, sometimes pain, at other times love, often fear.
They think of knowledge as being dragged around by these other things, as if it
were a slave. Does the matter seem like that to you? Or does it seem to you that
knowledge is a fine thing and what rules a man, so that if someone were to know what is
good and bad, he would not be forced by anything to act otherwise than knowledge
dictates, and that intelligence would be sufficient to save him?
Not only does it seem exactly as you say, Socrates, but it would be shameful for me of
all people [because I call myself a Sophist and say I educate men]
to say that wisdom and knowledge are anything but the strongest in human
affairs"
(Protagoras 352a).
If the Triparite Theory is true, the view Socrates expresses here is false: knowledge of what is good and what is bad is not "sufficient to save" a man. As we will see in the next three lectures, Plato believes that in addition to having this knowledge the soul must be just.
Perseus Digital Library
Plato's
Republic,
Theaetetus,
Timaeus,
Philebus
Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott,
A Greek-English Lexicon
βούλησις, boulēsis, noun, "willing"
επιθυμία, epithymia, noun, "appetite"
ἐπιθυμητικός, epithymētikos, adjective, "desiring, coveting, lusting after"
Plato uses ἐπιθυμητικός and θυμοειδής as adjectives corresponding to the
επιθυμία and the θυμός.
θυμοειδής, thymoeidēs, adjective, "high-spirited"
θυμός, thymos, noun, "strong feeling or passion"
λογιστικός, logistikos, adjective, "skilled or practiced in cacluating"
μουσική, mousikē, noun, "art over which the Muses preside"
ὄρεξις, orexis, noun, "appetency, conation, including ἐπιθυμία, θυμός, βούλησις"
πρόνοια, pronoia, noun, "foresight"
"Socrates thought that
there is no such thing as acting against one's own better judgment. ...
Plato, Aristotle, and their followers, on the other hand, believed that
such cases could not be explained as purely intellectual failures, that one
had to assume that besides reason there is an irrational [= nonrational] part of the soul with
its own needs and demands which may conflict with the demands of reason and
which may move us to act against the dictates of reason, if reason has not
managed to bring the irrational part of the soul firmly under its control"
(Michael Frede, "The Stoic Doctrine of the Affections of the Soul," 96.
Norms of Nature: Studies in Hellenistic Ethics, 93-100. Cambridge University
Press, 1986).
"[I]t is not the task of reason to provide us only with the appropriate knowledge and
understanding; it is also its task to provide us with the appropriate desires. To act
virtuously [for Aristotle] is to act from choice, and to act from choice is to act on a desire of reason.
The cognitive and the desiderative or conative aspects of reason are so intimately linked
that we may wonder whether in fact we should distinguish, as I did earlier, between the
belief of reason that it is a good thing to act in a certain way and the desire of reason
which this belief gives rise to, or whether, instead, we should not just say that we are
motivated by the belief that it is a good thing to act in this way, recognizing this as a
special kind of belief which can motivate us, just as the Stoics think that desires are
nothing but a special kind of belief"
(Michael Frede, A Free Will. Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought, 49-51.
University of California Press, 2011).