Teleology in Nature
Against the Explanations the Inquirers into Nature give
Unlike θεολογία ("theology"), for example, or other
compound Greek words such as φυσιολογία, there is no ancient Greek word that transliterates
as teleology.
Aristotle thinks that sensible substances
have their specific behaviors (the behaviors common to members of the kind)
for an end and that
the end is the benefit the behavior brings.
This is part of the picture in the Timaeus, but Aristotle understands it a new way.
We can build to Aristotle's understanding by first considering a passage in the Phaedo where Socrates hopes for the kind of explanation Plato later gives in the Timaeus.
Socrates and Anaxagoras
"One day I heard a man reading from a book, as he said, by
Anaxagoras,
that it is intelligence (νοῦς) that arranges and is the cause (αἴτιος) all things.
I was pleased with this
cause, and it seemed to me to be somehow right that intelligence should
be the cause of all things, and I thought that
intelligence in ordering all things must order
them and place each thing as it is best for it to be"
(Phaedo 97b).
νοῦς is an Attic form of νόος. It means "mind."
Sometimes νοῦς translated as "intellect" or "intelligence," where this is the power
the mind possesses. This has its roots in the translation of νοῦς into Latin as intellectus.
"My glorious hope, my friend, was quickly snatched away from me. As I went on
with my reading I saw that the man made no use of intelligence, and did not
assign any real causes for the ordering of things, but mentioned as
causes air and ether and water and many other absurdities. And it seemed to me
it was very much as if one should say that Socrates does with intelligence
whatever he does, and then in trying to tell the causes of everything I do, to
say that the reason that I am sitting here is because my body consists of
bones and sinews, because the bones are hard and are separated by joints, that
the sinews are such as to contract and relax, that they surround the bones
along with flesh and skin which hold them together, .... He would mention
other such causes for my talking to you: sounds and air and hearing, and a
thousand other such things, but he would neglect to mention the true causes,
that, after the Athenians decided it was better to condemn me, for this reason
it seemed best to me to sit here and more right to remain and endure whatever
penalty they ordered"
(Phaedo 98b).
Anaxagoras is the author of "books" (βίβλοι). Socrates, in the Apology,
says that they can be bought cheaply (26a).
Socrates says that "I made all haste to get hold of the books and read them
as quickly as possible" (Phaedoe 98b).
When Socrates says that "the man made no use of
intelligence," he is making
a joke Anaxagoras's expense. In addition, and more importantly,
he is saying that Anaxagoras does not explain what happens
when "intelligence" orders things. In the Timaeus,
Plato tries to supply the explanation in terms
of the divine maker.
"It is unnatural that either fire or earth or any other
such element should cause existing things to be or become well and
beautifully disposed; or indeed that those thinkers should hold such a view.
Nor again was it satisfactory to commit so important a matter to accident
and chance. Hence when someone said that there is mind in nature, just as in
animals, and that this is the cause of all order and arrangement, he seemed
like a sane man in contrast with the haphazard statements of his predecessors.
We know Anaxagoras adopted this view"
(Metaphysics I.3.984b)
In the Phaedo, in a story about his past interest in the inquiry into nature,
Socrates
says that when he was young he hoped
to learn from Anaxagoras something he very much wanted to know. Anaxagoras
talked about
νοῦς ("mind"), and Socrates thought this
would mean that Anaxagoras was going to explain
that things are as they are because this way is best. He found, though, when he read on in the book,
that
Anaxagoras made
no use of his νοῦς.
Socrates has the traditional thought that order is the result of the behavior of a mind or intellect. He expected that Anaxagoras would give such an explanation but to his surprise and disappointment found that Anaxagoras gave no "real causes for the ordering of things."
Socrates gives an analogy to show what Anaxagoras does in his explanations that Socrates takes to be so absurd. He says that it is as if Anaxagoras had said that Socrates has a mind but then makes it do no work in his explanations for why Socrates does what he does. Instead of mentioning the "true causes" to explain why Socrates is sitting in jail, Anaxagoras would blather on about Socrates' bones and sinews being situated in a certain way.
The "true causes," Socrates thinks, are what would figure in his doing "with intelligence whatever he does." For his sitting in jail, as he is doing in the Phaedo, he explains that he is doing this because after the Athenians convicted him, "it seemed best to [him] to sit here [in jail] and more right to remain and endure whatever ever penalty they ordered."
(After Socrates was convicted, he had to wait in jail for his execution until the ship of Theseus returned to Athens (Phaedo 57b). Crito, his friend from childhood, had visited him in this intervening time and offered to help him escape. Socrates declined (Crito 44b).)
Socrates, in doing "with intelligence whatever he does," is acting for something. He is acting for the sake of the good. He thinks that what is good and thus is beneficial is what is "right" and that this is to sit in jail to wait for the penalty the Athenians ordered.
In the Gorgias, as we have seen, Socrates advocates for this understanding of action.
"Then when do you say it is better to do these things? Tell me where you draw the line.
I would rather that you, Socrates, answered that.
Well then I say, Polus, if you prefer to hear it from me, that it is better when these things are done rightly, and worse when wrongly"
(Gorgias 470b).
"Polus and I, if you, Callicles, recollect, decided
that everything we do should be for the sake of what is good. Do you agree with
us in this view—that the good is the end of all our actions, and it is for its
sake that all other things should be done, and not it for theirs? Do you add
your vote to ours, and make a third?
I do.
Then it is for the sake of what is good that we should do everything, including
what is pleasant, not the good for the sake of the pleasant.
Certainly.
Now is it in every man's power to pick out which sort of pleasant things are
good and which bad, or is professional skill required in each
case?
Professional skill, Socrates"
(Gorgias 499e).
The "For Something" is in Nature
"It is absurd to think that nothing comes to be for the sake of
something unless that which
effects the change is observed to deliberate. In fact, even the
art does not deliberate. And if
the art of making ships were present in the wood, it would make the same way as in nature.
So, if the for something is present in the thing produced
by art, so it is in the thing produced by nature
(Physics II.8.199b).
Aristotle thinks that an "accidental" (αὐτόματος) outcome is one that
occurs concidentally and that "luck" (τύχη) is the special case of an accidental outcome that happens in
connection with a choice someone makes. If, to use one Aristotle's
examples, a man goes to market and happens to see someone who owes him money,
we says that it was a matter of luck that he collected the debt.
"Among the products of thought, such as a house or a statue, some never are due
to accident or necessity but always the for
something; others, like health and security, may also be due to
luck"
(Posterior Analytics II.95a).
"It is clear, then, that when any causal agency coincidentally produces a
significant result outside its aim, we attribute it to an accidental outcome;
and in the special cases where such a result springs from deliberate action
(though not aimed at it) on the part of someone capable of choice, we may say
that it comes about by luck"
(Physics II.VI.197b).
Aristotle also thinks the explanations the inquirers into nature give
are inadequate, but he takes the argument further than Socrates.
Aristotle thinks that these inquirers, with their explanations,
eliminate what he describes as the "for something" (ἕνεκά του) in nature.
Aristotle wonders why we should believe that the for something is in nature rather than that nature works in the way the inquirers into nature suppose in their explanations.
We can see him doing this in the following passage from Book II of the Physics.
"The question arises why we should suppose nature acts for something and because it is better, but
as Zeus rains
not to make the corn grow but of necessity the rising vapor
is condensed into water by the cold, and then must descend, and coincidentally,
when this happens, the corn grows. If corn on the threshing floor is ruined, it
does not rain for this, so that the corn is ruined. This is coincidental to the
raining. What, then, is to stop the parts of nature from being like this--the
front teeth of necessity growing sharp and suitable for biting, the back teeth
broad and serviceable for chewing, not coming to be for this, but by
coincidence? And similarly for the other parts in which the for something seems
to be present. So that when things turned out just as they would had they
come to be for something, but instead were suitably set together as an
accidental outcome, they survived. Otherwise,
"Empedocles says that at the beginning of Love [one the two forces
he thinks moves things in nature] there were born first, as it
happened by chance, the parts of animals, like heads, hands, and feet,
and that later these came together, that is, composites of cattle and human
beings. And all the parts that were assembled with one another in such as way
as to be capable of surviving became animals and continued to exist because
they satisfied each other’s needs, the teeth cutting and chewing the food, the
stomach digesting it, the liver turning it into blood. And a human head,
coming together with a human body, ensures the survival of the whole, but with
a cow’s body it is not adapted and is destroyed. For whatever did not come
together according to an appropriate relation perished. In this same way
everything happens now too"
(Simplicius, Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics; D 152; DK B 31 61).
"These are Empedocles's words: Many grew double of face..., races of man-prowed cattle,
while others sprang up inversely, creatures of cattle-headed men"
(Aelian, On the Characteristics of Animals XVI.29,
D 156; DK 31 B 61).
"At that time the earth tried to create many monsters
with weird appearance and anatomy—
androgynous, of neither one sex nor the other but somewhere in
between;
some footless, or handless;
many even without mouths, or without eyes and blind;
some with their limbs stuck together all along their body,
and thus disabled from doing anything or going anywhere,
from avoiding harm or obtaining anything they needed.
These and other such monsters the earth created.
But to no avail, since nature prohibited their development.
They were unable to reach the goal of their maturity,
to find sustenance, or to copulate.
For we see that creatures need the concurrence of many things
in order to be able to reproduce and to spread their progeny"
(Lucretius, On the nature of things V.837).
Titus Lucretius Carus (first century BCE). On the nature of things is
an exposition (in Latin) of Epicureanism.
"[I]t may be asked, how is it that varieties, which I have called incipient
species, become ultimately converted into good and distinct species, which in
most cases obviously differ from each other far more than do the varieties of
the same species? ... [The answer is that this occurrence follows] inevitably from the
struggle for life. Owing to this struggle for life, any variation, however
slight and from whatever cause proceeding, if it be in any degree profitable to
an individual of any species, in its infinitely complex relations to other
organic beings and to external nature, will tend to the preservation of that
individual, and will generally be inherited by its offspring. The offspring,
also, will thus have a better chance of surviving, for, of the many individuals
of any species which are periodically born, but a small number can survive. I
have called this principle, by which each slight variation, if useful, is
preserved, by the term of Natural Selection, in order to mark its relation to
man's power of selection"
(Charles Darwin,
On the Origin of the Species. III. Struggle for Existence, 61;
published in 1859).
they perished and still perish, as Empedocles says of the man-headed calves"
(Physics II.8.198b).
In the explanations in question, the "for something" is not present (just as "doing with intelligence" is not present in the explanation Socrates imagines Anaxagoras would give to explain why he is sitting in jail). Necessity, in these explanations, makes animals develop in the ways we see, and because the for something is not part of the process, it is a coincidence that this development benefits them. It is a coincidence that these animals use their front teeth for biting and that their front teeth come in sharp and thus are suited for biting.
The problem, Aristotle thinks. is that this not a coincidence. Coincidences are infrequent.
"This account or one like it might give us pause, but it is impossible for things to be this way. The things mentioned, and all things due to nature, come to be as they do always or for the most part, and such things are not the outcome of luck or an accidental outcome. We do not think it is luck or chance that there is a lot of rain in winter, but only if there is a lot in August; nor that there are heatwaves in August, but only if there is a heatwave in winter. If, then, things seem to be coincidental outcomes or for something, and the things we are discussing do not coincide as accidental outcomes, they must be for something. But all such things are due to nature, as the authors of the views under discussion themselves admit. The for something, then, is present in things that are and come to be by nature" (Physics II.8.198b).
Forward in the Physical Works
This shows to Aristotle's satisfaction that "nature acts for something and because it is better," but it does not show how. Sensible substances are forms in matter. They have their specific behaviors because their forms are the particular organizations of the matter they are.
Now we need to see the connection between these organizations and the benefit they bring to members of the species. Aristotle does not believe in natural selection. He does not think the organizations that endure are the ones where the individuals with these organizations have a greater chance of surviving and passing on their organization to their offspring.
Instead, in his explanation of the connection, Aristotle argues for the existence of a divine being he describes as the "first mover, which is unmovable" (πρῶτον κινοῦν ἀκίνητον).
This being is part of a perspective Aristotle shares with Socrates and Plato but not so much with us. Aristotle has the traditional thought that the explanation of order and regularity is in terms of intelligence, but he does not accept the divine maker in the Timaeus.
To understand this in Aristotle, it is helpful first to see a behavior in human beings he thinks benefits them. This behavior is the development of reason. Aristotle thinks that human beings naturally develop reason as they mature from children into adults, that they use reason for knowing and choosing, and that the reason they develop is suited for this use.
The soul in human beings, as Aristotle understands it, is the cause of this behavior. He argues in On the Soul, as we will see in the next lecture, that the soul is the form of living things. It is their nature and the "starting point of change and staying unchanged" in them.
Perseus Digital Library
Aristotle,
Metaphysics.
Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon
αὐτόματος, automatos, adjective, "just happens, without cause"
ἕνεκα, heneka, preposition followed by the genitive case, "on account of, for the sake of, because of, for"
ἕνεκά του, heneka tou, "for something" (του is an indefinite singular pronoun in the genitive case)
συμβαίνω, symbainō, verb, "to come together, coincide"
συμβεβηκός, noun, nominalization of a perfect passive participle from of σῠμβαίνω, "accident, coincidence"
κατὰ συμβεβηκός, "by accident, coincidentally"
σύμπτωμα, symptōma, noun, "thing that has befallen"
τέλλω, verb, "to make arise, accomplish"
τέλος, noun, "fulfilment or completion"
τύχη, tychē, noun, "luck, fortune"
Charlton T. Lewis, Charles Short,
A Latin Dictionary:
forma, noun, "form, contour, figure, shape"
species, noun, "the outward appearance, outside, exterior; shape, form, figure"
"This thing they call the ἰδέαν, a name
already given it by Plato; we can correctly term it form (speciem)"
(Cicero, Academica I.30).
Arizona State University Library. Loeb Classical Library:
Aristotle, Physics
Empedocles, Early Greek Philosophy, Volume V: Western Greek Thinkers, Part 2