ARISTOTLE

The First Great Platonist and Plato's First Great Critic

Plato, 427-347 BCE.   Aristotle, 384-322 BCE.



Raphael Sanzio da Urbino (1483-1520), The School of Athens
Plato and Aristotle, the School of Athens
Plato points to a "higher" reality. Aristotle points forward. He accepts what he regards as the central parts of Platonism, but he also is a critic who eliminates its excesses.

Plato holds a copy of the Timaeus, a late dialogue devoted to cosmology. Aristotle holds a copy of a work in ethics.

The titles TIMEO and ETICA on these books translate from Italian into English as TIMAEUS and ETHICS.
Aristotle belongs to the Period of Schools. He entered Plato's Academy in 367 BCE when he was seventeen and remained until Plato's death in 347 BCE. In 335 BCE, Aristotle founded his school in the Lyceum (a gymnasium located outside and east of Athens's city wall).

The Aristotelian Corpus

As we now have it, the works in the Aristotelian corpus are esoteric (written for members of the school) and organized systematically into roughly three subjects. The logical works come first. They are followed by the physical works. The ethical works are last. From this systematic ordering, there is no straightforward way to recover a chronological ordering.

This makes the Aristotelian corpus different from the Platonic corpus.

We can see in Plato's dialogues the development of his thought in his reaction to Socrates, and although some of the arguments are more challenging than ones we encounter in everyday life, he did not write his dialogues expressly for insiders. He models his early dialogues on conversations Socrates had, and these conversations were not with philosophers.

The works in Aristotle's corpus are also less finished than many of Plato's dialogues. Some of Aristotle is easy to read, but a lot of it is little more than a series of compressed notes.

Platonist and Plato's Critic

These differences will not make us change our strategy for understanding Aristotle. Socates was Plato's greatest influence. Plato is Aristotle's. He spent twenty years in the Academy. So, just as we assumed Plato was trying to understand what was right and correct what was wrong in what Socrates thought, we are going to work through the Aristotelian corpus in roughly its systematic order with the assumption that Aristotle is trying to understand what is right and correct what is wrong in what he learned from Plato during his time in the Academy.

We can see this happening in parts of Aristotle's Physics.

The Physics is the first work in the physical works and an inquiry into the truths that hold throughout nature. Subsequent works in the physical works are discussions of specific parts of nature. On the Soul, for example, which we will consider in a later lecture, is the first work in the physical works about the nature of "ensouled" and thus living things. ψυχή is the Greek noun translated as "soul." ἔμψυχος is formed with the prefix ἐν ("in"). It means "alive."

Aristotle, with his interest in nature, is following Plato against Socrates.

Plato disagreed with Socrates about whether knowledge of the reality of things is part of being wise. Whereas Socrates thought all we need to know is what is good and what is bad, Plato thought that the soul forgets itself when it decends into the body and that the best life a soul can live in the body is one of managing its time so that as much as possible it recovers the knowledge of reality it once possessed when it was apart from the body.

Plato tries to describe this reality in the Timaeus. This traditionally is a late dialogue. Plato wrote it late in his life and after Aristotle had become a student in the Academy.

Timaeus, not Socrates, leads the discussion. He is the "best astronomer and has made it his special task to know about the nature of the whole" (27a). He begins with "the origin of the cosmos" and ends "with the generation of man." In this discussion, he explains the existence of sensible things Timaeus describes sensible things as the "offspring" of the forms and the receptacle (Timaeus 50d). He supposes that before the god created the cosmos, the traditional elements (fire, water, earth and air) were "without reason and measure" (Timaeus 53a), that the god formed them to "be as beautiful and excellent as possible" (Timaeus 53b), and that he constructed the rest of the cosmos from them.

"For at that time [before the demiurge did his work] nothing had a share in these proportions save by chance, and there was nothing at all worthy of being called by the names we now use, such as fire or water or any of the others. Rather he first set all of these in order, then constructed this universe from them; a single living being containing within itself all living beings both mortal and immortal. He himself was indeed the artificer of the divine beings and he commanded his own offspring to undertake the creation of the mortals. And they, imitating their father, received the immortal beginning of soul, then fashioned a mortal body in a globe around it, for it, and bestowed the entire body as its vehicle and also built on another form of soul in the body: the mortal form" (Timaeus 69b),
in terms of forms (27d), the divine maker ("artificer" or "demiurge" (δημιουργός) who is supremely good and brings a cosmos into existence as like himself as possible (30a), and the "receptacle" (ὑποδοχή) that becomes like the forms (49a).

We can begin to understand a large part of Aristotle's contribution to philosophy if we understand him as trying to remove the problems he sees in this picture of reality in the Timaeus. He accepts, as we will see, that there is teleology in nature but rejects that things are the way the are because of the actions of a divine maker. He understands the existence of living things in terms of forms but does not think these forms exist as Timaeus describes them. Instead of the existence of the receptacle, Aristotle has what he calls matter.

Existence in the World of Natures

Aristotle refers to forms in his description of the kind of existence he takes substances to possess. Humans have a kind of existence. Their existence is human. Aristotle thinks the same is true for other sensible substances. They each have a kind of existence, but these kinds are all instances of the kind that characterizes something as a sensible substance.

Aristotle, as we will see, in thinking about how substances exist, thinks that

• sensible substances have natures
• this nature is the organization of the material that constitutes the substance
• this organization of the material is a form

The details here will take the next several lectures for us to begin to understand, and it is not clear that Aristotle has these details worked out in a way that make sense.


δευτέρα φιλοσοφία, "second philosophy"
πρώτη φιλοσοφία, "first philosophy"
We can now, though, if we look back to the discussion in the logical works, begin to see why Aristotle understands his study of sensible substances in the physical works as "second philosophy" and what translates more literally as "second love of wisdom."

Aristotle thinks that a goal in physics is knowledge of the forms of sensible substances that gives us an understanding we exhibit in what he calls a "demonstration" (ἀπόδειξις).

Demonstrations in Physics

The logical works are organized to show us what demonstrations are. The Categories is first. It discusses terms, the parts of sentences. On Interpretation is second. It discusses sentences, the parts of deductive arguments. The Prior and Posterior Analytics are next. The Prior Analytics discusses these arguments, and the Posterior Analytics discusses demonstrations.

For demonstrations, definitions are starting-points. Definitions specify the The Latin essentia and substantia translate οὐσία.

οὐσία is a noun formed from a participle of εἶναι ("to be") and a noun-forming suffix -ία. Because Latin had the suffix but not the participle of esse ("to be"), the participle essens was introduced into the language so that the word essentia could be formed in imitation of the way οὐσία is formed in Greek. Seneca, in his Epistles 58.6, uses essentia and cites the authority of Cicero to justify it as a Latin word.

For the imperfect in τὸ τί ἦν εἶναι, see Smyth 1901-1902 and "F" in the entry for εἰμί in Liddell and Scott.
the "essence" or "what it is to be" (τὸ τί ἦν εἶναι) for substances of the kind, and a demonstration is a deductive argument (a "syllogism" (συλλογισμός)) that explains why substances of this kind have their specific behaviors (the behaviors common to members of the kind).


"A deduction (συλλογισμός) is an argument in which, certain things having been supposed, something different from those supposed results of necessity because of their being so" (Prior Analytics I.1.24b). "The reason why we must deal with deduction before we deal with demonstration is that deduction is more universal; for demonstration (ἀπόδειξις) is a kind of deduction, but not every deduction is a demonstration" (Prior Analytics I.4.25b).

"The starting-point of every demonstration is the what it is (τὸ τί ἐστιν)" (On the Soul I.403a).

In a syllogism, there are three terms: "subject" (S), "middle" (M), and "predicate" (P). Each premise has one term in common with the terms in the conclusion. In the major premise, the predicate is the common term. In the minor premise, the subject is the common term.

It is customary to write the major premise first. This can seem unnatural until one realizes Aristotle does not write "All M are P." Instead, he writes "P is predicated of all M." So when the premises and the conclusion are expressed in the form Aristotle uses, the demonstration

All M are P
All S are M
----
All S are P

takes the form

P is predicated of all M
M is predicated of all S
----
P is predicated of all S


"For if A is predicated of all B, and B of all C, A must necessarily be predicated of all C" (Prior Analytics I.4.25b).

Aristotle's theory of the syllogism is major achievement in logic that was only surpassed in the last hundred years or so.
Consider human beings, for example. Suppose that rational animal is "what it is to be" a human being. This gives us a definition. It appears as the second premise. The first premise tell us that the power to use sensations to form beliefs is part of being a rational animal.

Rational animals can use their sensation to form beliefs.  (All M are P)
Human beings are rational animals.                                   (All S are M)
----
Human beings can use their sensations to form beliefs.     (All S are P)

Together, these premises tell us why human beings form beliefs in terms of sensesations. They are material organized as a rational animal, and part of organizing material this way is organizing it so that it has power to form beliefs in terms of their sensations.

Notice that this way of trying to understanding sensible substances makes no mention of laws of nature. Aristotle does not have the idea that there are laws that govern and explain the behavior of all objects, irrespective of the kind to which these objects belong.

This is one important way the world appears differently to us than it does to Aristotle.

The Life of a Philosopher

Now we can see the interpretation that motivates the organization of the Aristotelian corpus.

Plato, in the Phaedo, as we saw, makes Socrates describe the φιλόσοφος as someone who devotes his life to possessing knowledge of forms and describe these forms as the unchanging, invisible reality of things we grasp not through the senses but in the exercise of reason.

   "Is the reality itself (αὐτὴ ἡ οὐσία), whose reality we give an account in our dialectic process of question and answer, always the same or is it liable to change? Does the equal itself, the beautiful itself, what each thing itself is, the reality, ever admit of any change whatsoever? Or does what each of them is, being uniform and existing by itself, remain the same and never in any way admit of any change?
   It must necessarily remain the same, Socrates.
   But how about the many things, for example, men, or horses, or cloaks, or any other such things, which bear the same names as those objects and are called beautiful or equal or the like? Are they always the same? Or are they, in direct opposition to those others, constantly changing in themselves, unlike each other, and, so to speak, never the same?
   The latter, they are never the same.
   And you can see these and touch them and perceive them by the other senses, whereas the things which are always the same can be grasped only by the reasoning of the intellect (τῷ τῆς διανοίας λογισμῷ), and are invisible and not to be seen?
   Certainly that is true.
   Now, shall we assume two kinds of existences, one visible, the other invisible?
   Let us assume them, Socrates" (Phaedo 78c).

Aristotle applies this idea to sensible substances. He thinks that these substances have an unchanging reality, that this reality is what it is for them to be, that we know this reality in reason, and that this knowledge is the basis for the account we give in demonstrations.

This helps us see why Aristotle thinks of physics as "philosophy" (φιλοσοφία).

It does not, however, explain why he thinks it is second philosophy and thus is second to first philosophy. To understands this "secondness," we need to take a closer look at how Aristotle understands sensible substances and the existence of substances more generally.

This, when we look at it, will takes us much further into the corpus. It takes us to what is known as Aristotle's Metaphysics. This a collection of books between the physical and the ethical works in the organization Andronicus is thought to have imposed on the Aristotelian corpus. These books contain an attempt to get the knowledge of reality Aristotle in the Nicomachean Ethics argues is part of the best life a human being can live.

Thinking about Aristotle

We have a strategy for thinking about Aristotle.

We are going to see how he supplies missing details in the thought he knew from his time in Plato's Academy and how he removes what he regards as its mistakes and excesses.

To see how Aristotle does this, we are thinking about his reaction to picture of reality in the Timaeus. In this dialogue, Timaeus explains the existence of living things in the cosmos in terms of forms and the work of a supremely good divine craftsman. We are trying to understand what part of this picture Aristotle accepts and what part he rejects.

As we will see in the next lecture, a part he rejects is how the forms of sensible substances exist.




Perseus Digital Library

Plato, Theaetetus, Timaeus
Aristotle, Metaphysics

Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon

ἀπόδειξις, apodeixis, noun, "showing forth, making known, exhibiting"
ἐξωτερικός, exōterikos, adjective, "outer" (a comparative of ἔξω, exō, adverb, "out")
ἐσωτερικός, esōterikos, adjective, "inner" (coined to correspond to ἐξωτερικός)
κόσμος, kosmos, noun, "order"
φιλοσοφία, philosophia, noun, "love of wisdom"
συλλογισμός, noun, "computation, calculation"

Arizona State University Library: Loeb Classical Library:
Aristotle, Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, Posterior Analytics, Physics




"Aristotle wants to hold on to the metaphysical primacy of objects, natural objects, living objects, human beings. He does not want these to be mere configurations of more basic entities, such that the real things turn out to be these more basic entities. But to look at an object [as Aristotle thinks the inquirers into nature do] just as the configuration of material constituents transiently happen to enter into is to look at the material constituents as the more basic entities" (Michael Frede, "On Aristotle's Conception of the Soul," 146. Essays on Aristotle's De Anima, 93-107).

"Horses are a kind of beings, and camels are a different kind of beings, but neither horses nor camels have a distinctive way of being, peculiar to them; they both have the way of being of natural substances..., as opposed to, e.g., numbers which have the way of magnitudes..." (Michael Frede, "The Unity of General and Special Metaphysics: Aristotle's Conception of Metaphysics," 85-86. Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 81-95).

"Aristotle's view of the world is such that the behavior of things in the celestial spheres is governed by strict regularity dictated by the nature of the things involved. But once we come to the sublunary, grossly material sphere in which we live, this regularity begins to give out. It turns into regularity 'for the most part,' explained by the imperfect realization of natures in gross matter. What is more, these regularities, dictated by the natures of things, even if they were exceptionless, would leave many apsects of the world undetermined" (Michael Frede, A Free Will, 28).




move on go back